07/30/25

Looking at Hugh Ross’s Book (2023) “Rescuing Inerrancy” (Part 2 of 25)

0009 How so?

Forty years after the Chicago Statement on Biblical Inerrancy is published, theologians are figuring ways to accommodate deniers by re-contextualizing the affirmations.

0010 I love sentences like that.

If a speaker utters that sentence from a podium at a science and religion conference, everyone nods in agreement.

0011 The scientists, sitting on one side of the auditorium, are interested in postulating extra-Biblical sources for Genesis 1-11, comparing the Creation Story to evolutionary science and finding it well… like I said… a flight of fancy, showing that the Biblical accounts are not historical in the modern sense of the word, and saving the best for last, guessing who the “redactor” must be.

These interests stem from the doctrine of scientific inerrancy and the somewhat foggy promise that scientists will become the high priests and priestesses of the emerging big(il)lib civilization.

That’s big government (il)liberalism.

The bigger that the government gets, the more illiberal the cult becomes.

0012 Christian theologians, sitting on the other side of the auditorium, are interested in using grammar and the milieu of ancient Near Eastern civilization to bury the hatchet of Biblical inerrancy and retain positions in the coming… how shall I say it?.. civilizational reorganization.

0013 I now ask, “Is there a certain ambiguity to the key word in Ross’s title.”

How can the term, “inerrant”, apply to both science and the Bible?

0014 May I recall a concept proposed by Razie Mah in How To Define The Word “Religion”, available at smashwords and other e-book venues?

Definition3 brings a spoken term2 into relation with the possibility of meaning, presence and message1.

Say what?

Okay, it helps to start with A Primer on the Category-Based Nested Form and A Primer on Sensible and Social Construction.  The category-based nested form manifests four statements.  The final statement goes like this.  A triadic normal context3 brings a dyadic actuality2 into relation with the monadic possibility of ‘something’1.  The subscripts correspond to Peirce’s categories of thirdness, secondness and firstness.  So, the statement also says, “Thirdness brings secondness into relation with firstness.”

0015 Here is a way to script the category-based nested form along with its application to definition.

Ah, look, the actuality2 in the application is the spoken word, “inerrancy”2.

0016 Not to rush the issue, but I may now ask, “Does this definition of ‘inerrancy’ apply to article 18, mentioned above?”

The answer is “Yes, as seen in the following figure.”

0017 The normal context of definition3 brings the actuality of the spoken word, “inerrancy”2, into relation with the possibilities of ‘meaning, presence and message’1.

0018 For the theologian, the meaning is history in the widest sense of the word.  In short, history serves as a witness, testifying to what happened.  The preservation of testimony through oral tradition may not be perfect, but those imperfections are expected for the operations of an oral tradition.  In that respect, apparent flaws serve as evidence of preservation across generations.

0019 Presence is much more difficult to assess.  Presence must concern the revelation itself.  Presence is what happened, stated plainly or “exoterically”.  Presence is also what happened, in regards to what cannot be stated plainlybecause witnesses cannot situate the content of their experiences.  The technical term is “esoteric”.

In Shakespeare’s play, Hamlet, the apparently insane and distraught prince stages a play for the court that re-enacts the murder of his father.  Genesis 1-11 is not much different.  We are in the court, watching a play, completely unaware that what is happening on stage really happened.

Oh, but someone in Hamlet’s audience knows.  The murderer was there when it happened.

0020 Message is also exoteric and esoteric.

For example, everyone knows that “day” means day.  Yet, the same word may send an esoteric message about a span of time very different than a rotation of planet Earth… or the rising and setting of the sun.

That raises the question, “Who was there to witness the signs contained in each Genesis day?”

0021 What does article 18 say concerning what it denies?

How do the deniers regard “biblical inerrancy”?

Here is one way to look at it.

0022 Science is inerrant, not the Bible.

In terms of meaning, Genesis is not history in the modern sense.

In terms of presence, Genesis has nothing to do with the evolutionary sciences.  The word, “no thing” is synonymous with “no presence”.

In terms of message, Genesis is like any other mythology in the civilized ancient Near East.  Some Christians (such as theologian William Lane Craig) may call it “mytho-history”.  And, that label makes sense, in so far as myths are historical beings.  Well, it also makes sense in so far as a myth may descend from a real historic event.  But, one cannot reconstruct the historic event from the myth.  That must come from an extra-biblical source… er… hypothesis.

07/29/25

Looking at Hugh Ross’s Book (2023) “Rescuing Inerrancy” (Part 3 of 25)

0023 The category-based nested form for the actuality of the spoken term, “Biblical inerrancy”, comports with Ross’s introductory argument.  At the same time, it does not.

Ross portrays a theodrama where a conclave of Protestant theologians meet in Chicago and set a standard.  Later, theologians start to compromise in the face of deniers.

He extends the theodrama to include the past few centuries.

0024 To this examiner, the theodrama is much older.   The separation of… what?… what the modern theologians will affirm… and what the modern theologians will deny…. has a mytho-history.  And, this now-esoteric theodramatic development is very much in evidence during the thirteenth century, the saeculorum when Saint Thomas Aquinas “baptized” the philosophy of Aristotle, whose writings had just been looted from Islamic jurisdictions by Christian Crusaders.

Or, were Aristotle’s writings “liberated”?

0025 Hmmm, before I go there, I want to dwell of the other key word in Ross’s title: “rescue”.

Here is a picture of what rescuing Biblical inerrancy may involve.

0026 As for meaning, Genesis 1-11 serves as an honest witness to the start of our world and our current Lebenswelt.  Obviously, these are not the same.  There is a disjuncture between Genesis 2.3, where the Creation Story closes, and Genesis 2.4, where the Primeval History begins.

Whoa!  “Primeval history” labels Genesis 1-11.  Doesn’t it?

Not in this examination.

Here, the Creation Story is Genesis:1 to 2.3.  The Primeval History is Genesis:2.4 to 11.

Keep that terminology in mind.

It plays a part in any rescue.

0027 As for presence, the Creation Story is a sign of the evolutionary record.  Ross does not fully articulate that concept in this book.  But, what Ross calls “moderate concordism” sounds like presence to me.  Just as Hamlet presents his play to the court in order to raise the awareness of one member of the audience, the person who killed his father, so God presents the Creation Story in order to raise the consciousness of a particular audience in our modern theodrama, the deniers.

Who could have imagined?

What crimes are the deniers guilty of?

I hope that they are not anything like the crimes committed by Adam and Eve.

0028 Finally, in regards to message, I have to ask, “What is it about spoken words?”

In the Creation Story, God speaks and nature (which is not God) constructs a reality that manifests God’s words.

In the Primeval History, there is a serpent with no hands, who speaks in such a way as to completely fool poor Eve, who walks right into a legal trap.

Oh, Eve will not “die”, because that is not how the serpent defines the word, “to die”.  In fact, the serpent has all sorts of alternate definitions to apply to the act of eating fruit from the tree of the knowledge of good and evil.  None of them carry the suggestion that Eve keep the seed of that fruit in order to plant it outside of Eden, once she and Adam get tossed off the premises.

0029 It makes me wonder whether that is precisely what Eve does.

Okay, I admit, Ross does not go there.

Instead, the title says it all: Rescuing Inerrancy: A Scientific Defense.

I ask, “What does the spoken word, ‘inerrancy’ mean?  Why does it need to be ‘rescued’?  What does a ‘scientific defense’ entail?”

0030 In our postmodern world, the titular terms and my list of questions entail explicit abstraction.  “Inerrancy”, “rescue” and “scientific defense” are terms that hand-talking ancestral hominins could never sign… or manual-brachial word-gesture.  Why?  What is there to picture or point to?

Hand-talk words picture and point to their referents.  So, the meaning, the presence and the message of a manual-brachial word-gesture involves implicit abstraction.  The referent is implicit to the gesture-word.  The referent is what the gesture-word pictures or points to.

That is not the case with speech-alone talk.

Spoken words cannot picture or point to anything.

07/28/25

Looking at Hugh Ross’s Book (2023) “Rescuing Inerrancy” (Part 4 of 25)

0031 Spoken words are purely symbolic labels.

I ask, “What happens to labels over time?”

One of the quirky theologians of the 20th century, Henri de Lubac, notices that the meanings, presences and messages1underlying spoken words2 change over centuries.  He focuses on the words, “nature” and “grace.  Both these words are explicit abstractions.  They both must be defined3.

0032 What about the term, “inerrancy”?

The first six chapters of Ross’s book (one through six) are devoted to “Biblical inerrancy” and its companion “dual revelation”.

The next five chapters (seven through eleven) argues that the first step in the rescue of “Biblical inerrancy” is concordism.  Concordism is the doctrine that um… the two revelations of… is it?… grace and nature?… or Bible and science?… are in harmony, if, for no other reason, they pertain to the same thing.

0033 I suppose that is why the old distinction between grace and nature, which is older than Saint Thomas Aquinas (1224-1274 AD), seems relevant.

0034 “Grace” goes with “Biblical inerrancy”.  Chapter six discusses this connection.  The Psalms declare that the Lord’s word is flawless and true.  Jesus embodies the life and the truth.

In a weird sort of way, “flawless” goes with “life”.  That would be an esoteric meaning, presence and message.  Life is not flawless unless… dare I say… it is compared to death.

Even a mortally wounded creature is alive… until… dead.  After I binge-watch dozens of medical podcasts on the most grotesque medical conditions, I marvel that people are alive.  There are so many things that can go wrong.  That is where truth comes in.  The multitude of subagencies within the agent remain true, living, and (relatively speaking) flawless, until, gasp, grace no longer inflows.

0036 “Nature” goes with “scientific inerrancy”.  Here, the thing itself (the noumenon) is disregarded.  The observable and measurable facets of the thing (its phenomena) are regarded.  Ideally, a disciplinary scientific language brings mathematical and mechanical models into relation with data (that is, observations and measurements of phenomena).

To many scientists, when a model works really well, it takes on a truth, a life and a flawlessness of its own.  It can take the place of the noumenon, the thing itself.  Until, of course, it is proven to be inadequate.  Newton’s mechanical physics is a case in point.  It worked really well until physicists could not account for the energy spectrum of light coming from a pinhole in a black metal box with a heated interior.  How crazy is that?

We still use Newton’s mechanics today, but almost all research goes into figuring out those odd exceptions.  The exceptional field is called “quantum mechanics”.  Quantum mechanics investigates light, among other things.  Atomic and subatomic nature is known through quantum mechanical models.

0037 The upper hylomorphe marks the beginning and the end of my examination of Ross’s text.

The lower hylomorphe suggests that maybe Henri de Lubac is on target.

07/26/25

Looking at Hugh Ross’s Book (2023) “Rescuing Inerrancy” (Part 5 of 25)

0038 Inerrancy is tied to dual revelation.  Two aspects of one reality are revealed.  At the start, these two aspects are grace and nature.

0039 The philosophy of Charles Peirce enters here.  He proposes three categories: firstness, secondness and thirdness.  The category-based nested form contains all three categories.

Here, I want to drill down on secondness.  Secondness contains two contiguous real elements.  For Aristotle’s hylomorphe, the two real elements are matter and form.  The contiguity is placed in brackets for proper notation.  What word describes the contiguity between matter and form?  I choose the much abused term, “substance”.  A thing is matter [substance] form.

0040 Now, scholastics of the early medieval period (say, in the centuries leading to and including the founding of universities in Europe) express a theological hylomorphe that complements Aristotle’s hylomorphe.

Here is a picture.

0041 Of course, a modern may object that “grace” is not like matter because it is not material.

However, in reply, I note that “grace” is being, which stands at one end of a spectrum between relationality and materiality.  I could have written the following, “A purely relational being [substantiates] a natural form.”

Oh, the objections do not stop there.

The same modern may object that “nature” is not susceptible to immaterial, purely relational beings.

To which I reply, “Sign-relations are purely relational beings and creatures in nature are always dealing with signs.  Indeed, biologist Jakob von Uexkull comes up with a technical word for any living creature’s world of significance.  The term is ‘Umwelt’.  Yeah, the noun is capitalized in German.  Each noun is like an an-Noun-cement.”

0042 Now, I ask, “Why does Aristotle offer his hylomorphe as the first step in natural philosophy?”

Here is the answer, as far as I can see.

The normal context of Aristotle’s philosophy3 brings the actuality of the hylomorphe, matter [substance] form2, into relation with the potential of the material, efficient, formal and final causes1.

A person encounters a thing.  An inquirer may understand this thing2, starting with matter [substance] form2.  Understanding provides a normal context3 and potential1.

0043 Now I ask, “Why do the early schoolmen offer their hylomorphe as the first step in bringing the revelations of the Old and New Testaments into harmony with the rationality of Greek philosophy?”

Obviously, the revelations of the Old and New Testaments enter into Greek natural reasonings and redeem them.  The revelations of Jerusalem bring Greek philosophy to life.

0044 Okay, when I want to understand how grace [inflows] nature2, I place this hylomorphe into a normal context3 and a potential1.

How do I do this?

I take a guess.

Yes, that is a reasonable guess.

0045 However, this guess leads to another question, asking, “If grace2 is like matter2 and nature2 is like shape2, then what label do I put for the equivalent to Aristotle’s ‘thing’2, given the normal context3 of the Holy Spirit3 and the potential for ‘bringing forth good’1?”

Perhaps, the human as an image of God?

Well, whatever the label may be, it is not scientific.

07/25/25

Looking at Hugh Ross’s Book (2023) “Rescuing Inerrancy” (Part 6 of 25)

0046 Does science have metrics to distinguish the phenomena of life from, say, the phenomena of death?

If so, there must be a caveat.

The phenomena of life indicate that the noumenon, life, is present.  But, these phenomena cannot objectify the thing itself.

I call this caveat, “Kant’s slogan”, because, if any Western philosopher is worthy of being falsely accused, that person is the German philosopher, Immanuel Kant (1724-1804 AD).

In other words, Kant may not explicitly state this slogan, but he comes close enough for the slogan to stick to him.  Slogans can be like tar-babies in this regard.  Once you touch a tar-baby, you are stuck with it.

Not surprisingly, that reminds me of Christians conjunct science.

0047 Kant’s slogan expresses what is of the Positivist’s judgment.  The Positivist’s judgment contains three elements: relation, what ought to be, and what is.

The relation is the positivist intellect.  The positivist intellect is imbued with thirdness, the realm of normal contexts. The positivist intellect has a rule.  Metaphysics is not allowed.

What ought to be is the empirio-schematic judgment.  In the empirio-schematic judgment, disciplinary language (relation, thirdness) brings mathematical and mechanical models (what ought to be, secondness) into relation with observations and measurements of phenomena (what is, firstness).  The empirio-schematic judgment is imbued with secondness, even though, technically, it should belong to thirdness.  After all, judgments are triadic relations.

What is is Kant’s slogan, rendered as a dyadic structure.  The structure appears to belong to secondness, the realm of actuality, but it really belongs to firstness, the realm of possibility.  Why?  The noumenon and its phenomena cannot be regarded independently, unlike matter and form, as well as grace and nature.  So, what is of the Positivist’s judgment does not depict two independent real elements.  The thing itself and its observable and measurable facets can be distinguished, but not separated.

0048 Here is a picture of what is of the Positivist’s judgment.

0049 Oh, there is a clue in this figure.

Aristotle’s thing goes with the noumenon.  So does grace [inflows] nature.

Science builds models on the basis of observations and measurements of phenomena.

Science ignores the noumenon because the thing itself cannot be reduced to what can be observed and measured.

0050 The question that I now address wonders, “How do I get from the dyad (in secondness) in the cloud to the noumenon (in firstness) that belongs to what is in the Positivist’s judgment?”

My starting point is grace [inflows] nature, rather than matter [substance] form.

Grace [inflows] nature belongs to secondness, the dyadic realm of actuality.  In order to bring this dyad into the noumenon, in the monadic realm of possibility, grace must be separated from nature.  That separation must be so complete that grace can potentially be regarded as totally independent of nature.  The same goes with nature.  Nature will need to be regarded as totally independent of grace.

0051 Here is one way to picture the trajectory.

0052 Before Aquinas, grace [inflows] nature describes… what?… health, well-being, redemption, happiness, the living human being?  By the time of Aquinas in the 1200s, the two labels, “grace” and “nature” are regarded as distinct and separate.  Grace [inflows] nature no longer indicates a living thing.  Rather, each term indicates its own ‘thing’.

In the centuries following Aquinas and before the mechanical philosophers of the 1600s, the distinction and separation becomes routine.

0053 From the above figure, it seems that the dyad saying that grace [is distinct and separate from] nature should lead to two associations.  Grace should associate to the noumenon.  Nature should associate to phenomena.

This does not happen, because the Positivist’s judgment is yet to be ideated.

0054 Instead, the separation solidifies.  After all, the terms, “grace” and “nature” are different terms, so they must refer to separate things, rather than real elements that constitute a thing.  Eventually, western Christendom will explore some very strange concepts, such as matter without form and form without matter.  But, the reification of these two spoken words begins by attributing completely distinct and separate referents to “grace” and “nature”.

0055 By the time of Galileo Galilei (1564-1642 AD), everyone agrees.  There are two books of revelation, the Bible (filled with grace) and the world (the stuff of nature).

07/24/25

Looking at Hugh Ross’s Book (2023) “Rescuing Inerrancy” (Part 7 of 25)

0056 At this point,  judgment cannot be avoided.

Here is the general structure of judgment as a triadic relation.

0057 A relation (category) brings what ought to be (category) into relation with what is (category).  When each of the three elements is uniquely assigned to one of Peirce’s three categories, the judgment becomes actionable.  Actionable judgments unfold according to their categorical assignments.  Thirdness becomes normal context3.  Secondness enters actuality2.  Firstness glides into potential1.

0058 What about this general agreement that is in the Zeitgeist in Europe between the so-called “Reformation” (1500s) and the so-called “Industrial Revolution” (1800s).  The agreement that “grace” and “nature” are distinct and separate (relation) anchors this element in secondness.

Everyone agrees that the separation is actual.  Plus, separation characterizes the relation between “grace” and “nature”.

What about the other elements of the judgment?

Of course, “grace” should go with what ought to be and “nature” with what is.

Here is a picture.

0059 The categorical assignments to “grace” and “nature” set the stage for the historical discussion in Ross’s book.

07/23/25

Looking at Hugh Ross’s Book (2023) “Rescuing Inerrancy” (Part 8 of 25)

0060 Let me start with nature as thirdness and grace as firstness.

0061 Yes, this judgment is actionable.

Nature as what is will become the normal context3 of an actionable judgment.

Grace as what ought to be will enter the realm of possibility1.

Here is a picture of the resulting nested form.

“Grace” and “nature” have separate referents.  These referents now occupy different positions in a category-based nested form.

0062 To start, the actuality2 looks awkward.  The normal context of nature3 is separate from and distinct from the potential of grace1.  Is that enough?  I don’t think so.  When the normal context is nature3, the possibility of grace1should be close to zero.

Why would this be so?

The logics of thirdness are exclusion, complement and alignment.  Grace does not complement or align with nature because it is distinct and separate.  So nature3 as a normal context will strive to exclude grace1 as a possibility.

I ask, “Is there a thing2 that represents the dyadic actuality portrayed above, in a convincing manner?”

The first item that comes to my mind are organizational protocols2.  Organizational protocols2 systematically exclude chance events, which would include moments of grace1, in the normal context of nature3.

0063 If that is so, then organizational protocols2 actualize the exclusion of the potential of grace1.  After all, exclusion is one of the logics of thirdness.  So, I wonder, “What would go into the slot for possibility, that further indicates that grace1 is excluded?”

Well, what about science, especially the philosophy of the mechanical philosophers?

Unfortunately, the empirio-schematic judgment, when unfolded into a content-level category-based nested form, looks like it would go into the slot for protocols2b.

0064 So, what if I elevate nature3 to the perspectivec level and put scientific inquiry2 into the contenta level?  Then, scientific inquiry2a provides models1c that contribute to protocols2c and exclude grace as a perspectivec-level potential1c.

The nice feature of the content-level is that it fulfills the scientist’s self-impression that his work entails a search for truth.  The logos3a (the word that is eventually codified in specialized disciplinary languages) brings the actuality of scientific inquiry2a (manifesting the protocols2c of the empirio-schematic judgment2c) into relation with the potential for ‘truth’1a.  Truth is not the same as grace.  Truth1a is… well… what science reveals1a.

0065 I am only missing the situation level, which must belong to the scientist.

The interscope is a category-based nested form composed of category-based nested forms.  See A Primer on the Category-Based Nested Form and A Primer on Sensible and Social Construction, by Razie Mah, available at smashwords and other e-book venues.

Here is how to state the above figure.

On the perspective level, the normal context of nature3c brings the actuality of protocols2c into relation with the possibility of ‘models’1c.  The models1c contextualize both scientific specializations2b and scientific inquiry2a.

On the situation level, the normal context of expertise3b brings the actuality of specialized jobs and research positions2binto relation with the potential of ‘institutionalizing scientific inquiry’1b.  Scientific work becomes more and more professional during the nineteenth and twentieth centuries.  Today, academic certification “guarantees” expertise3b.

On the content level, the normal context of logos3a (or the “words” of a disciplinary language) brings the actuality of scientific inquiry2a (the empirio-schematic judgment) into relation with the potential of ‘truth’1a (the validity of models accounting for observations and measurements of phenomena). Of course, the terms, “logos” and “truth” also have more expansive connotations.

0066 In sum, I have learned that the widespread acceptance of the distinction and the separation of grace and nature since the recovery of Aristotle by Saint Thomas Aquinas has significant consequences.  The distinction and separationare regarded as real as the distinction and separation of two referents or “things”.  These two “things” are products of explicit abstraction.

Explicit abstraction is potentiated when humans adopt speech-alone talk during the first singularity, starting around 7825 years ago.  No precise date has been set.  Before that transition, all human cultures practice hand-speech talk, which combines the iconicity and indexality of hand-talk with the symbol-generating qualities of speech.  Unlike hand talk, speech cannot picture or point to anything.  So, speech serves as an adornment to hand talk, even as it takes on a life of its own during the Upper Paleolithic.

0067 Hand-talk and hand-speech talk facilitate implicit abstraction in the Lebenswelt that we evolved in.

Speech-alone talk facilitates explicit abstraction in our current Lebenswelt.

0068 The three-level interscope pictured above allows the inquirer to conduct implicit abstraction based on explicit terms occupying locations in a purely relational structure called “an interscope”.  In the interscope, perspectivec brings situationb into relation with the potential of contenta.  This interscope derives from imbuing nature (what is) with thirdness.

07/22/25

Looking at Hugh Ross’s Book (2023) “Rescuing Inerrancy” (Part 9 of 25)

0069 Let me go to grace as thirdness and nature as firstness.

Here is a picture of the judgment.

0070 As before, the relation is imbued with secondness, so this term will enter actuality2 for the following category-based nested form.

0071 Now I wonder, “What is an actuality2 that coheres to the normal context3 (of grace) while standing distinct and separate from its potential1 (of nature)?”

If I choose the actuality2 of redemption2, then I can be assured of the possibility ‘that nature is excluded’1, in the normal context of grace3.

Redemption2 does not have much to do when it comes to nature1, in the same way that protocols2 do not have much to do with grace1.

0072 The abduction does not stop there, because redemption2, as an actuality, engenders a nested form on the adjacent lower level.  Redemption2 seems to situate the normal context of salvation3 bringing the actuality of a personal relationship with God2 into relation with the potential of the church1.

At the moment, I am uncertain whether the two levels correspond to situation and content or to perspective and situation.  Let me continue.

0073 With this pairing of category-based nested forms in tow, I wonder about the possibility of ‘excluding nature’1.  Is this potential compatible with the potential of the ‘church’?  Oh, I can think of a better term than “excluding nature”.  How about the word, “creation”?

Ah, if “creation” is the perspective-level potential1c, then “creation1c” contextualizes both the Bible2a and theological formulations of my personal relationship with God2b.

There is the resulting interscope.

0074 On a perspective level, the normal context of grace3c brings the actuality of redemption2c into relation with the possibility of ‘creation’1c.

On the situation level, the normal context of salvation3b brings the actuality of a personal relationship with God2b into relation with the potential of ‘the church’1b.  Theologians and pastors are crucial in manifesting the situation-level normal context3b and potential1b.

On the content level, the normal context of the logos3a brings the actuality of the Bible2a into relation with the possibility of ‘revelation’1a.

07/21/25

Looking at Hugh Ross’s Book (2023) “Rescuing Inerrancy” (Part 10 of 25)

0075 Once Christendom gives up on the dyadic actuality of grace [inflows] nature, then both “grace” and “nature” become distinct and separable.

Once Christendom agrees that “grace” and “nature” are distinct and separable, then that determination becomes a relation held in common by two apparently independent judgments.  The relation does not belong to thirdness, the realm of normal contexts.  Instead, the relation belongs to secondness, the realm of actuality.

Once the relation is assigned to the category of secondness, two parties arise.  One party insists that grace3 excludes nature1, in the same way that a normal context3 may suppress a possibility1.  The other party is convinced that nature3excludes grace1, in the same way that a normal context3 may rule out a possibility1.

Finally, the elevation of nature or grace entangles content, situation and perspective, resulting in the three-level “nature” and “grace” interscopes.  Because each perspectivec-level normal context3 excludes the other perspectivec-level normal context3, these three-level interscopes take on lives and traditions of their own.

0076 The fact that these two parties live in the same civilization is the topic of chapter 1 of Ross’s book.  This chapter is titled “Surprising Theological Developments”.  Science does not seem to be hindered.  Theology begins to wonder about the possibility of ‘creation’1c in the face of the apparent infallibility of ‘evolutionary models’1c.

In chapter 2, Ross considers the concept of dual revelation, calling to mind the guises of grace and nature.  He asserts that nothing that scientists can discover about the world, when rightly understood, will contradict what is written in the pages of the Bible.  Truth (in nature) does not contradict truth (in grace).  That is a reminder of the beautiful early medieval dyad of grace [inflows] nature.  But, maybe, Ross’s assertion does not go far enough to bring us back to the Middle Ages.

0077 In chapter 3, Ross isolates several articles from the Chicago Statement on Biblical Inerrancy that pertain to these two parties.

Article 19 goes like this.

0078 In chapter 4, Ross claims that disturbing concessions are being made by Christian theologians in regards to such consensus statements.

These concessions are occurring on the perspective level of grace3c.

Which possibility is more real?  Creation1c or evolutionary models1c?

The inerrancy of the Bible covers the entire text, including the Creation Story and the Primeval History.  But, “inerrancy” does not mean that the Bible meets the standards of “without error” for naturalism, evolutionism and scientism.  “Inerrancy” means “living” as opposed to “dead”, “flawless” compared to “corrupt”, and “honest” as opposed to “deceptive”.

But, theologians are not interested in rocking the boat, so to speak.  Fudging creation1c in order to support the actuality of redemption2c in the normal context of grace3c does not seem so terrible, especially when creation1c becomes more “realistic”, in the scientific sense of the word.  Creation1c is expressed in myths that are consistent with the written origin stories of the ancient Near East3a.

0079 As far as the evolutionary sciences are concerned, the potential of ‘model’1c that underlies protocol2c involves elevating models1c into the place of noumena, the things themselves1c.  Once, this is done, a model1c [can be objectified as] its phenomena, and protocols2c are empirio-schematic recipes that validate that each model is supported by the data.

0080 Say what?

On one hand, a noumenon (the thing itself) [cannot be objectified by] its phenomena.

On the other hand, a model taking the place of the noumenon [can be objectified as] its phenomena.

0081 So, if ‘models’1c comport with ‘excluding grace’1c by taking the place of the noumenon, then what are the consequences?

I cannot imagine that the results are well… um… honest.  All the metaphysics of the Positivist’s judgment goes into the noumenon.

0082 What happens when I substitute a model for the thing itself?

Well, I lose all the metaphysical implications of what is for the Positivist’s judgment.

Even more disturbing, what if… um… the model is not the real thing?

Well, let scientists worry about that when the counterfeit becomes obvious.

Until then, the model1c must be placed into the slot for the noumenon in what is for the Positivist’s judgment, because the triumphant positivist intellect3a wills1a it1c.

Yes, to replace the noumenon (the thing itself) with a model (based on observations and measurements of phenomena) entails an act of will1a.

07/19/25

Looking at Hugh Ross’s Book (2023) “Rescuing Inerrancy” (Part 11 of 25)

0083 The start of chapter 4 suggests that the distortions occurring on the perspective-level of the interscopes of grace3cand nature3c may be due to the challenges of specialization.

Here is a comparison of the situation-levels.

0084 The theologian has knowledge about salvation3b.  Indeed, the theologian3b brings people into communion with God2b through the possibilities of ‘the church’1b.  However, the authority of the churches is now being challenged by those who do not view Genesis 1-11 as scientifically credible.

I suppose this lack of scientific credibility is what Ross intends to solve.

The problem is that revelation1a is not supposed to be scientifically credible.  It is supposed to be… um… revealing.

0085 The scientist has knowledge about a particular topic3b.  Expertise3b brings specialized tasks2b into relation with the potential of ‘an institutional setting’1b.  That ‘institutional setting’1b is not ‘the church’1b, even though it1b may be highly ideological.

Why would the world1b of scientific2b expertise3b be ideological?

Well, what does it take to say that a model should replace the thing itself?

Ah, it takes will power.

0086 So, what am I saying?

Well, here is a comparison of the content-levels for the interscopes of grace3c and nature3c.

0087 For grace3c, the normal context of the logos3a brings the actuality of Genesis 1-112a into relation with the potential of ‘revelation’1a.

For nature3c, the normal context of the logos3a brings the actuality of scientific inquiry2a into relation with the potential of ‘truth’1a.

0088 One beauty of these formulations is that both theology and science share a common content-level normal context3a.  The word, “logos”, means “word”, as well as “the study of…” and so on.

To me, “logos” is not like a gesture-word of hand talk, characteristic of the Lebenswelt that we evolved in.  “Logos” is not based on images or indications.  “Logos” does not convey the impression of an implicit abstraction.

Instead, “logos” is like the spoken word of speech-alone talk, characteristic of our current Lebenswelt.  “Logos” starts with purely symbolic labels.  “Logos” conveys the impression of explicit abstraction.

0089 Beauty is a transcendental.

So, I better watch out and look again.

Surely, beauty slips out of the vision when I consider what theologians and scientists are actually doing.  In chapter 4, Ross discusses what the theologians are up to.  But, the scientists are up to no good, as well.  The content-levels have changed in order to accommodate “pressures”.  Concessions must be made in order to keep one’s job.

0090 Surely, this comparison looks different than what was expected from the fact that grace and nature are distinct and separate.

But, this is what Christians are stuck with, in my version of Ross’s historical introduction.