05/10/25

Looking at Alexander Kravchenko’s chapter (2024) “A Constructivist Approach…” (Part 2 of 6)

1005 On top of that, in chapter seven of Pathways, Alexei Sharov offers another option.

In addition to [meaning], there are potential meanings and potential signs.  Potential meaning goes with [presence].  Potential sign associates to [message].

This is awkward, since the terms, “potential meanings” and “potential signs” take the contiguities out of their brackets (so to speak).

1006 Plus, the exercise of considering “potential meaning” and “potential sign” raises a question concerning how to square the normal-context of agent3 with the normal context of definition3.  To me, the agent3 contextualizes definition2(3) as integral to semiotic agency2.  So, somehow, the nature of spoken words2(2) gets imported into semiotic agency2 as a thing itself (or, should I say, “a noumenal overlay itself”?).

1007 Here is a picture.

The colors are suggestive, but misleading.  [Presence] is wholly contained within the semiotic of semiotic agency.  [Message] spans interventional sign-relation and semiotic agency.  The coloration reminds me that [message] is like passing through a portal to the SVs.  An interventional sign-object (SOi) [inters or infolds] the specifying sign-vehicle of semiotic agency (SVs).

Here is the trick. With [inters], the SOi enters from the Umwelt.  With [infolds], the SOi arrives from the Innerwelt.  [Inter] is not wholly contained within the agent.  [Infold] is.

That may be confusing.  And, the above figure exploits that confounding with suggestive, but misleading, coloration.

1008 What I have said concerning how [meaning] may be problematic fits the author’s bold assertion: Knowledge is a language game.

Meaning is like a substance, the contiguity between a manner of matter (the object of an exemplar sign-relation, SOe) and a manner of form (the vehicle of an specifying sign-relation, SVs).

Like [message], [meaning] is a portal.  The portal goes from the end terminus of semiotic agency, the goal2c (SOe), to the beginning terminus of the interventional sign-relation, the goal in action2c (SVi).

1009 At the same time, meaning1 is a potential that underlies a spoken term2 in the normal context of definition3.

1010 So, which is it?

Let the language games begin.

1011 The author relates that a century ago (say, around the 1920s, when the nature of empirical science is debated), linguistic theories of meaning display two fashions.  One academic style concerns how spoken expressions work in terms of symbol manipulation.  The other academic style concerns whether spoken expressions mean what dictionaries say they mean… that is, “semantic content”.

The author makes this accusation in section 8.1, titled, “Do We Ask The Right Kinds of Questions?”

1012 I find this a little funny, along with the author’s note, saying (more or less), “Human adaptive behaviors3 may be viewed as end-directed activities that construct semiotic agency2 as a capacity1 to generate such behavior3.”

Without the subscripts assigning Peirce’s categories, the note sounds perfectly circular.

With the subscripts, the statement transforms into a category-based nested form responsible for constructing semiotic agency2 as an actuality2.

This2 is semiotic agency2.

1013 Here is the trick.  “End directed activities” substitutes for “the interventional sign-relation”.

So, the interventional sign-relation [constructs] semiotic agency.

This dyad is a wonderful way to portray the biosemiotic noumenal overlay in speech-alone talk.

1014 Speech-alone talk is different from hand and hand-speech talk.

Hand talk pictures and points to its referents.

1015 In human evolution, hand talk becomes linguistic when manual-brachial icons and indexes become sufficiently distinct from one another as to constitute a system of differences.

Remember dictionaries?  They embody a system of differences.  Each written word differs from all other written words.  Symbols constitute systems of differences.  A finite set of symbols constitutes a symbolic order.  The symbolic order represented by a dictionary is… um… alphabetical.

Once routinized, manual-brachial gestures become symbols, they fall into a system of differences and become linguistic. Then, these linguistic gestural-words support grammar.  Grammar consists in symbolic operations within a finite system of differences.

So, hand talk refers by way of Peirce’s natural signs of icons and indexes (SOs).  Also, hand talk becomes linguistic when these icons and indexes become more and more symbolic (that is, distinct from one another).  Grammar consists of symbolic operations among hand-talk words.

1016 Hand and hand-speech talk belong to the Lebenswelt that we evolved in.

Speech-alone talk belongs to our current Lebenswelt.

Speech-alone words cannot picture or point to their referents.

1017 Speech-alone talk simply attaches a label to…. whatever… such as what the term, “end-directed activities” is supposed to mean.  Or, maybe I should say, mean, present and announce.

The spoken term, “end-directed activities” announces, “I am what constructs semiotic agency”. 

The same spoken term presents itself as belonging to the realm of actuality2.

The same spoken term has a meaning2 that arises from the potential of ‘the human capacity to generate adaptive behaviors’1 in the normal context of human adaptation3.

1018 So, here is the trick.  The term, “end-directed activities”, is just a label.

The interventional sign-relation [constructs] semiotic agency.

1019 Here is a picture.

1020 The interventional sign-relation allows us to imagine that end-directed activities reside “out there”.

But, [meaning] draws the inquirer’s gaze away from the end-directed action (SVi) back to the goal2c (SOe).

And, this is crucial, because the goal2c resides “in here”, within semiotic agency. 

05/9/25

Looking at Alexander Kravchenko’s chapter (2024) “A Constructivist Approach…” (Part 3 of 6)

1021 So, in this language game concerning theories of meaning, I end up with the appearance that “end-directive activities” reside “out there” (as the interventional sign-vehicle (SVi) expresses an agent’s goal2c in action) as well as “in here” (as the goal2c itself (SOe)).

1022 Dare I continue?

The author calls the SOe “objective” and the SVi “objective in parentheses”.

In this terminology, the goal2c (SOe) is “objective” and its expression2c (SVi) is “objective in parenthesis” because… well… any intervention can go wrong (so, it is better to put the objective in parenthesis).

1023 A rewarding feature of this modern nomenclature is that it allows a clean break between semiotic agency (the Innerwelt aspect) and the interventional sign-relation (the Umwelt and Lebenswelt aspect).

Here is a picture.

For the contiguities, [p] is [presence], [mn] is [meaning] and [mg] is [message].

1024 A clean break makes intellectual labors simpler when [message] is [inter] and more complicated when [message] is [infold].

When I speak to myself, I labor as semiotic agency produces a speech-act that serves as an intervention which activates my… um… semiotic agency.

Is the [message] [inter] or [infold]?

Does it have to be one or the other?

1025 The medieval scholastics come up with terms that are discussed in Looking at John Deely’s Book (2010) “Semiotic Agency” (appearing in Razie Mah’s blog for October, 2023).  The terms pertain to the levels of the scholastic interscope for how humans think.  The term, “subjective”, labels the content level, where SVs resides.  The term, “objective”, labels the situation level, where SOs is located.  The term, “intersubjective” labels the situation level, where SVe is located.  The term, “suprasubjective”, labels the perspective level, where SOe is located.

1026 Here is a picture.

1027 This implies that SOe [meaning] SVi is, for scholastics, “suprasubjective’ (that is, “subjective from a divine perspective”) and, for modern academics, the locus of both “objective” and “objective in parenthesis”.

In short, the biosemiotic structure of suprasubjectivity contains both objective goal2c (SOe) and its (objective) expression in the moment (SVi).

1027 As if to demonstrate the delicacy of this modern distinction, the author offers the example of spoken language as the arbitrary relation between two systems of differences, parole (speech in act) and langue (speech decoded). 

1028 Can the reader guess how these two systems of differences fit into the above diagram?

Here is what I figure.

1029 The information2b of semiotic agency is within the agent, even though it2b concerns what2a  apparently is located without.

For this reason, I may playfully modify information2b into -formation2b (SOs) [presence] in-2b (SVe)

If the goal2c is to say ‘something’, then SVi is parole, a speech act.  The parole (SVi) stands for an intention2a (SOi) in regards to what is happening3a operating on the potential of ‘something’ happening1a (SIi).  Of course, this intention2a(SOi) is not the same as the originating goal (SOe) and that becomes evident when spoken words are instantly decoded by a langue operator2a (SVs) as an event akin to sensation2a.

1030 That brings me (the examiner) back to [meaning] as the contiguity between an objective goal2c (SOe) and an (objective) parole (SVi).

05/8/25

Looking at Alexander Kravchenko’s chapter (2024) “A Constructivist Approach…” (Part 4 of 6)

1031 Have I avoided the author’s epistemological trap (section 8.2)?

Does what I am saying (SVi) seem to support what I think (SOe)?

At least, to a disinterested observer (SOi)?

1032 What am I wrestling with?

Here is a picture, relying on a combination of elements from Sharov and Tonnessen’s noumenal overlay and from the scholastic interscope for how humans think.

1033 I now proceed by way of example.

1034 I say to Daisy, “I guess that we are taking this duck home in order to see whether it lives.”

My expression2c (SVi) stands for my intentions in making the statement2a to Daisy (SOi) in regards to what is happening3a operating on the fact that ‘something’ has happened1a (SIi).  Daisy got what she wanted.  The other dog did not.  And now, I am Daisy’s master and assigned to make sense of this disaster.  I suppose that is why humans make such good pack-leaders for these domesticated wolves.

1035 I take off my waterproof jacket, toss inside down onto the ground, then place the still-breathing remains on the tarp2a (SVs).  The duck is not as heavy as I anticipated.  It is easy to carry home, even with Daisy on the leash and constantly wanting to check on it2b (SOs).  The duck is the “form” in “information2b” (SOs).  Its presence is contiguous with the… “in- “… of “information2b” (SVe).  Yes, I am in it2c (SOe) alright.  So, is Daisy and the ornamental duck who is seriously messed up.

1036 Daisy suspects what I am going to do2c (SOe) because I did the same for her.

Her suspicions make information2b pertinent, because it2b is bound to be salient3c((1c)) to our goal2c.  

1037 My written description of Daisy’s suspicions runs right into section 8.3 titled, “The Observer, the Observed, and the Problem of Interpretation”.

Would a biosemiotician say that he (or she) can observe and measure the sign-vehicles and the sign-objects in the following diagram?

1038 Yes, the SVs and the SOs become phenomena once the biosemiotic noumenal overlay is regarded as the thing itself.  My particular episode may serve as a case study.  See any article in The Journal on the Care of Injured Ducks.

Daisy is not cognizant that I plan (SVe) work up a case study to submit for publication.

Publish or perish!

1039 Is this where the author is taking this examiner?

Yes and no.

Yes, there is an epistemic cut between an organism’s observed adaptive response (SVi) and an observer describing the adaptive response in terms of sign-elements and claiming that an interpretation is plausible (SOi).  It seems as if what is plausible (SOe) derives from a sign-object (SOs) that all biological processes and entities have in common.

No, the epistemologist cries, “Cut!”

1040 Then, members of the audience look around asking, “Who said that?”

The heckler shouts, “I mean… cut between semiotic agency and the interventional sign-relation.”

Then, the well-certified members settle back in their chairs and cluck, “Yes, it is epistemic.”

Take a look at “yes” and see that the cut is incorrect.

05/7/25

Looking at Alexander Kravchenko’s chapter (2024) “A Constructivist Approach…” (Part 5 of 6)

1041 Epistemic?

Or empirio-schematic?

Where does the epistemic cut go?

Does empirio-schematics care?

1042 We can observe and measure the sign-vehicles and sign-objects in the following figure, once we have the following figure as a diagram of the thing itself.

Then, we can formulate models to account for the sign-interpretants.

1043 On one hand, the inquirer may treat the biosemiotic noumenal overlay as operational, consisting of three sign-relations, which constitute a spiral of semiosis through time.

On the other hand, the inquirer may regard each biosemiotic spiral phenomenologically, that is, as what the noumenon must be.

1044 With this in mind, I may look at one of the real elements that goes with [meaning], SVi, along with its counterpoint, SVs.

Parole2c (SVi) and langue2a (SVs) are worth considering.

Parole2c (SVi) is a vocal expression2c (SVi) that stands for the expression of an intention2a (SOi) in regards to a content-level normal context3a and potential1a (SIi).  Like the actions of an animal, parole (SVi) is a real event that generates a sign-object (SOi) that signifies like an icon, a picture that sends a message.

Parole2c (SVi) is a real event that belongs to the interventional sign-relation.  It’s counterpart, langue2a (SVs) initiates semiotic agency.

1045 Amazingly, over a century ago, Ferdinand de Saussure transforms the discipline of linguistics by proposing that spoken language consists of two arbitrarily related systems of differences, parole (SVi) and langue (SVs).

Here is one way to consider the proposition.

Parole, SVi, as an actuality2c on the perspective level, has a counterpart, langue, SVs, serving as an actuality2a on the content level.  SVi belongs to the interventional sign.  SVs belongs to semiotic agency.

1046 With that consideration in mind, suprasubjective parole2c, SVi, can be observed by a disinterested observer, and subjective langue, SVs, cannot.  But, does that invalidate the claim that SVs is phenomena?   No, langue2a, SVs, initiates the specifying sign-relation.  That is phenomenal.

Here, I add a caveat.  There is more than one way to portray parole and langue using diagrams of triadic structures.  Just saying….

1047 Nonetheless, in a complementary fashion, I may look at the other real element that goes with [meaning], SOe, along with its counterpart SOi.  Goal2c connects to [meaning].  Expression of intention2a associates to [message].

1048 This suprasubjective-subjective pair seems even more evolutionarily ancient than parole and langue.  The goal2c, SOe, terminates semiotic agency.  An expression of intention2a or the expression intended2a, SOi, satisfies the interventional sign-relation and activates a [message].  The goal2c (SOe) belongs to the Innerwelt.  The intended expression2a (SOi) belongs to the Umwelt (and for humans, the Lebenswelt).

Indeed, may I suggest that SOi is what a disinterested observer would objectify if he were not on the subjective level?

04/29/25

Looking at Arthur Reber, Frantisek Baluska and William Miller Jr’s Chapter (2024) “The Sentient Cell” (Part 2 of 4)

0611 Ah, I see a pattern.  The titular terms of “sentience” and “cell” label the same noumenal elements where subagents reside.  Plus, these are the elements that need to be modeled.  They are not the elements associated to phenomena.

0612 Here are the key words and their respective sign-interpretants.

The specifying sign-interpretant (SIs) derives from Kull’s criteria for semiotic agency (see points 0026 through 0037). Self-governance associates to a situation-level normal context3b and a choice of actions goes with situation-level potentials1b.

The exemplar sign-interpretant (SIe) is may be labeled, “salience3c,1c“, in order to avoid articulating (or explicitly abstracting) the perspective-level normal context3c and potential1c.  The descriptions in the preceding figure constitute my rough guesses.

After all, what does the spoken word, “salience”, mean?

Why is it present in this particular instance?

Does this particular word send a message?

0613 I suppose that I can compare my descriptions of the specifying and the exemplar sign-interpretants to the scholastic interscope for how humans think, appearing in Comments on John Deely’s Book (1994) “New Beginning” (by Razie Mah, available at smashwords and other e-book venues), as well as Looking at John Deely’s Book (2010) “Semiotic Animal” (Razie Mah’s blog for October, 2023).

John Deely (1942-2017) is quite the scholar.  His books plumb scholastic literature for insights into postmodern semiotics.

0614 What does he discover in these explorations?

He finds that Charles Peirce (in the 1800s) comes up with the same definition of the sign-relation as Baroque scholastic, John Poinsot (in the 1600s).

Quite a discovery.

He also sets the stage for Mah’s diagram of the scholastic interscope for how humans think.

0615 The following is a hybridization of terms from the S&T noumenal overlay and features from that scholastic interscope.

0616 At this point, the authors’ language-manipulations become more obvious.

Their title is “the sentient cell”.

The aim of their chapter is to model the cellular basis for consciousness.

And, right away, this examination associates the key titular terms to the sign-interpretants in Sharov and Tonnessen’s noumenal overlay.

Yes, these sign-interpretants contain subagents.

0617 The authors claim that life and sentience are coterminous (section 13.1 and 2).

Then (section 13.2.1), they assert that unicellular organisms have sensory and perceptual mechanisms (SIs).  They learn and remember (SIs and SIe).  They make decisions (SIe).

0618 Then (section 13.2.2), the authors explore how biomarkers play roles among these sign-interpretants.  These biomarkers include the actions (SOe(?)) by one subagent that serve as real initiating semiotic events (SVs) for another subagent.  One subagent sends a message.  The other subagent receives it.  A biomarker released from one subagent provides information to another subagent.  This information contributes to a goal that, for all practical purposes, both subagents have in common.

0619 At this point (section 13.2.3), the authors explicitly mention the term, “information”.

They note that biological information, unlike “information” in the computer sciences, is ambiguous.  Why?  The computer sciences focus on the transmission of information.  The biological sciences are curious how information2b(SVe) stands for a goal2c (SOe) with respect to making sense3c (or, should I say, “sentience”) enough to take action1c(SIe).  They also wonder how a real initiating event2b (SVs) stands for information2b (SOs) in regards to the living cell3b facing possible courses of action1b (SIs).

0620 In section 13.2.4, the authors insist that life and sentience cannot be attributed only to phenotypic expression of the cell.  Yes, DNA allows reproduction to unfold from a template.  But, the genome does not define the nature of biological agency.

What defines semiotic agency?

0621 May I compare the category-based nested forms for agent3 and definition3?

Perhaps, such a comparison would assist in addressing the question, “If a sentient cell is conscious… or is conscious by analogy to human consciousness… then what is the sentient cell conscious of?”

0622 Surely, the sentient cell is not conscious of its own membrane.

But, it would be if it were conscious.

The cellular membrane is precisely what is needed for both life and sentience.  So, the cellular membrane is a prime subagent.  It is a foundational subagent.  It is… so to speak… ground floor for both life and consciousness.  Along with a host of other subagents, the cellular membrane gives rise to sentience, but it is not conscious of itself.

0623 Does that answer the question? 

If life and sentience associates to sign-interpretants, then what the cell is conscious of must associate to the respective sign-vehicles and sign-objects.

How obvious is that?

04/28/25

Looking at Arthur Reber, Frantisek Baluska and William Miller Jr’s Chapter (2024) “The Sentient Cell” (Part 3 of 4)

0624 Here is a picture of what a sentient cell is “conscious” of, as it appears in a three-level interscope.

0625 Yes, this interscope is both a category-based and a semiotic arrangement.  The interscope is not suitable for empirio-schematic inquiry because science investigates actualities.  In Semiotic Agency, Sharov and Tonnessen fashion a way to express this interscope in terms of Peirce’s secondness.  The S&T noumenal overlay supports empirio-schematic research.

0626 Now, I want to take my examination in a different direction.

In section 13.2.5, the authors claim that non-biological entities cannot become sentient agents.  This claim reminds me of the problem faced by biologists, in contrast to physicists and chemists.  Semiotic agency2 is composed of both being (relationality) and matter (physicality).  Consequently, in order to understand the actuality of semiotic agency2, it2 must be placed in a normal context3 with potential1.

0627 Ironically, the same goes with the spoken word.

Here is a picture.

0628 The juxtaposition is suggestive.

0629 An agent3 and a definition3 both follow the logics of thirdness.  The logics of thirdness are exclusion, complement and alignment.  Here, one agent3 excludes other agents3.  The cell membrane2 plays a role in that exclusion.  Similarly, the definition3 of one spoken word2 must exclude the definitions3 of other spoken words2 .

Notably, definition3 does has not have anything like a cell membrane2.  Rather, spoken words (parole) constitute a system of differences3.  The Greimas square proves useful for teasing out how one spoken word is distinct from other spoken words.  (See points 0586 through 0591.)

0630 Semiotic agency2 and a spoken term2 follow the logics of secondness.  These logics include the laws contradiction and noncontradiction.  If a contradiction exists, then there must be a way to either resolve or formalize the contradiction.

For semiotic agency2, one source of contradiction comes from the hierarchy of agent and subagents, as well as cooperation (and competition) among subagents.  If the agent and the subagents have difficulty coordinating2, then the agent3 may fail in regards to its intentions1.

0631 But, what are those intentions1?

Are those intentions1 what the living cell3 is sentient of2?

If so, then I suppose that semiotic agency2 involves being conscious of ‘something’1 and this ‘something’1 could be labeled with spoken words2, as if a living sentient cell could speak.

0632 ‘Final causality’1 and ‘meaning, presence and message’1 follow the logics of firstness.  Firstness is inclusive and allows contradictions.  So, the intentions1 of an agent3 cohere to the meaning, presence and message1 of a… hmmm… spoken word2?

Uh oh.

The comparison starts to break up.  It is as if definition3 is what an agent3 does.  An agent3 actualizes something2 that may compare to definition2(3) in order to bring semiotic agency2 into relation with the possibility of ‘final causality’1.

What does this imply?

Is definition2(3) is built into semiotic agency2?

Can spoken words2(2) label what the agent3 is conscious of?

0633 To me, this suggests that final causality1 undergirds the actualities of semiotic agency2 through a passage into meaning, presence and message2(1), as if meaning, presence and message2(1) (now incorporated into semiotic agency2) reify final causality1 for the agent3.

0634 In other words, the agent3 defines2(3) through its life and sentience (SIs and SIe) actualities that it is conscious of2(2) (SVs, SOs, SVe and SOe) by embodying meaning, presence and message2(1) as manifesting the potential of ‘final causality’1.

Here is a picture.

0635 Does this make sense?

The entire nested form that we (humans in our current Lebenswelt) associate with definition3 becomes a characteristic of semiotic agency2.  Therefore, all the elements of how to define a spoken word enter into the realm of actuality2. Definition3 gets transubstantiated (a change of category) down to actuality2.  Meaning, presence and message1 gets transubstantiated up to actuality2.  And, the spoken word2 becomes what the living entity would be conscious of, if it were conscious2.

04/24/25

Looking at Vic Norris and Alexei Sharov’s Chapter (2024) “…How Bacterial Cells… Change… in Response to Various Signals” (Part 2 of 4)

0659 In section 14.3, the authors report evidence that supports the hypothesis.

0660 What do bacterial researchers observe?

The authors provide examples “hyperstructures” in Table 14.1.  These include cytoskeletal filaments, structures made from enzymes, microcomponents, membrane-associated structures, external appendages, DNA-containing structures, phase separation condensates and more.

0661 What do the hyperstructures tell the researcher?

Hyperstructures vary depending on how much energy is available… oh, I meant to say… nutrients are available.

So, the authors propose two temporal phenotypes, corresponding to the appearance of hyperstructures that use lots of energy (NE, non-equilibrium conditions) and ones that conserve current integrity (E, equilibrium conditions).

0662 Here is a picture.

0663 As one might suspect, the two models of hyperstructure maintenance (SIsand plasticity (SIe) work in tandem.  Some transitions from one temporal phenotype to another are easy.  Some are not so easy.

As one might have anticipated, a tremendous amount of scientific research has gone into almost all aspects of the hyperstructures, especially in regards to genomic regulation of bacterial DNA.  Empirio-schematic research abounds.  The problem is that research discoveries appear to have little in common.  It’s the problem of inquiry into each leaf occludes the reality of the tree.

0664 The authors provide an example, in section1 4.3.2, for the case when lactose is among the nutrients.

The lac operon, when expressed, contributes to NE hyperstructures.  Lactose… transformed into one isomer, allolactose… induces synthesis of the lac operon by binding to a LacI protein that clings to bacterial DNA and represses genomic expression.  Allolactose binds to LacI protein and changes it conformation.  The allolactose-bound LacI protein lets go of the strands of DNA that it is holding on to, providing the opportunity for formerly suppressed genes to be converted into mRNA.

In sum, for bacteria, lactose is both a nutrient and a cue (SVs) that ultimately says, “Fatten up and divide (SOe).”

0665 Section 14.3.4 describes cell-cycle hyperstructures and signaling.  That is to say, “The NE route.”  The density of scientific detail stuns the reader.  By my estimate, every two sentences summarizes a doctoral thesis.  In some paragraphs, every sentence boils down years of research by a doctoral student.  The section reads like a biochemical textbook.

After this tour de force of supporting evidence, the authors propose (in section 14.4) that semiotics can be used to explain cues and signals (SVs) in bacteria.

0666 This is where the authors stand today, in 2024, at the threshold of appreciating the um… message, presence and meaning… that biosemioticians observe and measure, in order to construct models of [being alive] and [sentience].

0667 As noted earlier, message (SVs), presence (SOs [&] SVe) and meaning (SOe) go with phenomena.

[Being alive (SIs)] and [sentience (SIe)] are what need to be modeled.

0668 What does this suggest?

The authors do not need to call for semiotics to explain cues and signals in bacteria.

Cues and signals are already specifying sign-vehicles (SVs) in the specifying sign-relation.

0669 Phenomena do not need to be explained.

Phenomena need to be observed and measured by humans who innately recognize sign-elements.  Plus, in our current Lebenswelt, we can label those sign-elements through explicit abstraction.

Biosemiotic observations and measurements (what is, firstness) are used to build models (what ought to be, secondness) within the purview of a scientific disciplinary language (relation, thirdness).  Such is the empirio-schematic judgment.

0669 Biologist Jakob von Uexkull intuitively senses this.  He does not have the advantage of Peircean diagrams of judgment or interscopes.  He cannot formulate the category-based nested form, where the normal context of definition3brings the actuality of a spoken word2 into relation with the potential of ‘meaning, presence and message’1.  But, he intuitively senses that definition3, spoken words2 and the potential of explicit abstraction1 fit into the conceptualization of semiotic agency.  That is why he frames his research in terms of theoretical biology and theories of meaning.

0670 Alexei Sharov and Morten Tonnessen, in their 2021 book, Semiotic Agency, also intuitively grasp this.  Unlike von Uexkull, they have loads of scientific research into biological systems, from the micro to the macro, at their disposal.  However, like von Uexkull, they do not have the disciplinary language to articulate… um… diagram… their noumenal overlay.

The only way to get to the point of picturing a noumenal overlay is to use diagrams of triadic relations.  One value of this examination comes precisely in the act of diagramming the authors’ arguments using triadic relations. Another value of this examination comes in the act of framing the history of biosemiotics as a historical response to the Positivist’s judgment.

0671 Yes, we stand on the shoulders of giants.

Charles Peirce (1839-1914), Edmund Husserl (1859-1939), Jakob von Uexkull (1864-1944), Thomas Sebeok (1920-2001) and John Deely (1942-2017) are giants upon whose shoulders both the authors (and Razie Mah) stand.

Nonetheless, diagrams can really be useful.

04/23/25

Looking at Vic Norris and Alexei Sharov’s Chapter (2024) “…How Bacterial Cells… Change… in Response to Various Signals” (Part 3 of 4)

0672 In section 14.4, the authors announce that they intend to use semiotics to explain cues and signals in bacteria.

On one hand, this is a fool’s errand, since cues and signals are specifying sign-vehicles (SVs) in the Sharov and Tonnessen noumenal overlay for semiotic agency.  They are real initiating (semiotic) events.

On the other hand, the very fact that the authors see a need to explain cues and signals in bacteria suggests that biosemiotics encompasses more than semiotic agency.  But what is that “something more”?

0673 Section 14.4.1 is titled, “Types of Semiosis, Signs and Effectors”.  The authors enter into a curious discussion concerning the appearance of greater and greater complexity on Earth.  Does semiotics play a role?  Does a change in semiosis accompany each major transition in evolutionary history, such as the transition from prokaryotic to eukaryotic life?

This debate winds its way into a ranking of semiosis into proto- or primitive semiosis and eu- or more advanced semiosis.  “Protosemiosis” applies to prokaryotes and “eusemiosis” to eukaryotes. 

0674 With that in said, there arises a question of definition.

In the Lebenswelt that we evolved in, language evolves in the milieu of hand talk.

The spoken word, “definition”, does not appear in the lexicon of any hand-talk language.

What is there to picture or point to?

So, where does the potential of meaning, presence and message come from?

Hand-talk words picture and point to their referents.  Meaning, presence and message are built into the natural-sign qualities of icons and indexes.  Icons and indexes promote implicit abstraction.

Speech-alone words cannot picture or point to their referents.  So, they must be defined.  That is where the nested form for definition turns out to be handy, as noted in Razie Mah’s e-book How To Define The Word “Religion” (available at smashwords and other e-book venues).

Speech-alone words label anything.  Purely symbolic labels permit explicit abstraction.

0675 Now, putting the evolution of complexity and the histories of particular labels aside, I return to the title of section 14.4., “Using Semiotics to Explain Cues and Signals in Bacteria”.  How do these keywords figure into the category-based nested form for definition?

Here is my guess, concentrating on the word, “explanation”.

0676 The author’s normal context of definition3 brings the actuality of a spoken explanation2 into relation with the possibility of ‘the meaning and semiotics (presence) of bacterial cues and signals (message)’1.

0677 Maybe I am too cautious in my associations.  The authors’ discussion seems to imply that the spoken word2should be “complexity” and the meaning should be “explanation”.

0678 If that is the case, then I may associate the author’s potential1 in definition3 to the bacteria’s potential1 of defining3 its own semiotic agency2 within its Umwelt3.

Explanation associates to meaning and to a bacterium maintaining its identity (SOe).

Semiotics associates to presence and to competitive competition maintaining one or another “temporal phenotype” (SOs[and] SVe).

Cues and signals associates to message and to what a bacterium encounters in its Umwelt (SVs).  At this juncture, a word coined by Jakob von Uexkull floats into view.  The Umwelt consists of all the sign-vehicles (SVsthat an organism can specify (SIs).

0679 What does this imply?

Well, let me display my more daring guess.

I ask, “Is the author’s focus on ‘complexity’, rather than ‘explanation’?  Does ‘complexity2‘ emerge from (and situate) the potential of explanations (meaning), using semiotics (presence), of cues and signals (message)1 in the normal context of definition3?  And, is it any coincidence that this label2 might apply to the S&T noumenal overlay?”

Does an increase in “complexity” entail an increase in “semiotic agency”?

04/11/25

Looking at Victoria Alexander’s Chapter (2024) “…The Emergence of Subjective Meaning” (Part 2 of 5)

0710 The intersection is a mystery because two actualities constitute one actuality.  Two category-based nested forms come together because their actualities apply to the same entity.

That is sort of confusing, especially when the single actuality2 has yet to be framed with a normal context3 and potential1.

0711 Let me consider each actuality2 on it own.

The first actuality is adaptation2.  Adaptation2 corresponds to the “darwinism” of “neodarwinism”.   The normal context of natural selection3b brings the actuality of an adaptation2b into relation with an organism’s niche1b.  The subscript, “b”, denotes the situation level.  So, there must be a content-level actuality2a (at a minimum).  The niche1b serves as the potential of that content-level actuality2a.

0712 Here is a picture.

0713 Yes, a niche1b is the potential1b of an actuality independent of the adapting species2a.

This formula applies to all sorts of “niches” fashioned within the boutiques of academic biology.

For example, “niche construction” fits the formula.  Beavers build a dam on a fast moving stream and the stream becomes a glen that provides plenty of food for the beavers.  The dam serves as a home.  Surely, when one dams a fast moving stream, the result is a glen that beavers can flourish in.  So, the term “niche construction” points to the fact that the actuality independent of the adapting species2a may be a process.  Plus, “niche construction” does not not stop there.  “Niche construction” indicates that the actuality independent of the adapting species2a may be purely relational structures, such as… um… triadic relations.

0714 I shudder to think what type of genus would adapt into a niche containing the potential of triadic relations.

0715 The second actuality is phenotype2.  Phenotype2 corresponds to the “neo” of “neodarwinism”.  The normal context of body development3b brings the actuality of a phenotype2b into relation with the organism’s genotype1b.  Or maybe, I should use the word, “genome1b“.  I guess the words are both different and the same.  The subscript, “b”, denotes the situation level.  DNA2a is the content-level actuality.

0716 Ah, the genotype1b is the potential1b of DNA2a.

0717 What else is curious about the two-level interscope for phenotype2b?

0718 The situation and content levels constellate a specifying sign-relation.  DNA2a (SVs) stands for the phenotype2b(SOs) in regards to body development3b operating on the variety of ways that DNA can be translated into proteins (the genotype1b) (SIs).

If this is the case, then I wonder, “Does this specifying sign-relation fit into Sharov and Tonnessen’s noumenal overlay?”

The answer is, “Yes, here is a picture.”

0719 Isn’t that curious?

The specifying sign-object (SOs) of phenotype2b does not take the inquirer to the biosemiotic fullness of semiotic agency. The exemplar sign-relation remains occluded.  Remember that the exemplar sign-relation associates with emergence (points 0280 through 0292).  It also associates with a goal2c that a biosemiotician recognizes as meaning2c.

0720 What does the biosemiotician recognize with respect to the “neo” component of neodarwinism?

The biosemiotician recognizes DNA2a (SVs) as message and phenotype2b (SOs) as presence.

0718 What about the “-darwinism” of “neodarwinism”?

The same principle applies.  The situation and content levels constellate a specifying sign relation.  The exemplar sign remains occluded.  An actuality independent of the adapting species2a (SVs) stands for an adaptation2b (SOs) in regards to natural selection3b operating on an organism’s niche1b (SIs).

04/10/25

Looking at Victoria Alexander’s Chapter (2024) “…The Emergence of Subjective Meaning” (Part 3 of 5)

0719 The first point (S) is stated in points 706 and 707.  NeoDarwinism may be a factor in evolution.  But, it is not the only one.

Maybe I went down the wrong rabbit-hole by raising the fact that neodarwinism is an intersection, because the lesson is not that intersections are mysterious (even though this lesson is true).  The lesson turns out to be that the two-level interscopes of natural selection3b and body development3b recapitulate the specifying sign-relation in independent ways.

0720 Why is that lesson important?

Consider the second point in the conclusion (T): The single actuality, the living being, operates on the basis of self-reinforcing cycles.

What does that imply?

Ah, the author shifts the reader’s focus in an unexpected manner.

Living being2 is the intersection of two actualities.

For non-human agency, self-reinforcing cycles are both adaptive and phenotypically expressed.

0721 What is natural selection selecting for?  Self-reinforcing cycles exploit opportunities and avoid dangers in regards to real initiating (semiotic) events.  If I drop a 2% glucose solution in the center well of a petri-dish containing a maze, the slime mold on the periphery of the dish will start making its way through the maze.  Glucose signals opportunity.

What is body development selecting for?  Self-reinforcing cycles allow the slime mold to move.  Also, receptors allows the slime mold sense a glucose gradient.  Plus, when the slime mold hits a wall and has to backtrack, a slime mold can deposit a chemical agent that says, “I’ve been here before.”  Yes, the slime mold is using its tools to solve the maze.

0722 So, how does this change of focus manifest when I return to the Sharov and Tonnessen noumenal overlays?

To me, self-reinforcing cycles replaces natural selection3b because the operations of these cycles3b pursue objective opportunities1b.

The adaptive presence2b is slime mold moving towards the source of glucose2a.  Glucose2a (SVs) sends a message, meaning food2c (SOe).  

0723 Here is a picture.

0724 Yes, the slime mold tries to find a way to the source of glucose (SOs) because glucose (SVs) objectively means food (SOe).

Why do I say, “Objectively.”?

In the introduction, section 15.1, the author distinguishes between objectivity and subjectivity.  Here, the presence of glucose is objective (SVs).  So is the reality that glucose means food (SOe).

Indeed, the biosemiotician considers these (SVs, SOs [&] SVe, SOe) to be the bases of phenomena.  Observations related to these phenomena go into modeling [the self-reinforcing cycles], as well as [objective salience], that is [SIs] and [SIe], respectively.

The author’s shift of focus, along with the example, transfers the concept of adaptation2b, within the normal context of natural selection3b and arising from a niche1b, into the milieu of semiotic agency.  The shift may be rhetorical, but it is effective nonetheless.  Adaptations go with the objective world, that is, the Umwelt as the world of signs.

0725 Well, then, what about “subjectivity”?

Well, maybe “subjectivity” can be called “relative objectivity”.

Relative to what?

The slime mold in the petri-dish.

0726 Here is a picture.

0727 “Subjective” is the right word in so far as, from a modern point of view, “subjective” means “self”.  The scholastics offer a different view, “subjective” means “the subject that has the attention of the self”.  Indeed, the latter view associates to the real initiating (semiotic) event (SVs).

As before, capturing attention of a slime mold in a petri dish2a (SVs) stands for its sensing, moving and marking2b(SOs) in regards to self-reinforcing cycles3b manifesting the slime mold’s subjective capabilities1b (SIs).  Plus, the exemplar sign-relation is now relevant.  The goal2c is to solve the maze (SOe) that the researcher has imposed.

0728 And, that raises the question, “If the slime mold were to be conscious, what would it be thinking?”

I suspect that the answer would be the objective opportunity and its salience.